Critique of Theonomy: A Taxonomy
T. David Gordon
T. David Gordon, “Critique of Theonomy: A Taxonomy,” Westminster Theological Journal Vol. 56:1 (Spring 1994),Westminster Theological Seminary, 1994, pp. 24-45.
I.
Introduction
1.
Distinguishing Theonomy from Theonomists
One
of the most difficult aspects of polemical theology is being sure that what is
being evaluated is a distinctive viewpoint, not the individuals holding the
viewpoint. Of necessity, when evaluating a given view, one examines those
dimensions that distinguish it from other views. It would inevitably be
lopsided, then, to confuse a criticism of a view with a criticism of those who
hold it. Presumably, those who hold a distinctive view also embrace many other
views that are identical with those shared by the church catholic. Individual
Theonomists are not intended to be the point of an examination such as this;
rather, what is evaluated is the viewpoint that distinguishes Theonomy from
other approaches to biblical ethics.
2.
Distinguishing Theonomy from Christian Reconstruction
As
socioreligious phenomena, Theonomy and Christian Reconstruction are closely
related. The individuals involved in the one are ordinarily involved in the
other. However, theologically and religiously they can be distinguished.
Christian Reconstructionists exist in a variety of forms, and are ordinarily
united in their belief that the Western world, and especially the United States,
has departed from the Judeo-Christian ethical basis that once characterized its
public discourse, with devastating results. Positively, Reconstructionists wish
to see the United States return to a more biblical approach, or even a
more Judeo-Christian approach, to the issues of civil life. Theonomy is
more specific than this, though it does not disagree with it. Theonomy wishes to
see every nation conform its civil practices to those revealed in the
Mosaic legislation. Thus, Theonomy is more comprehensive than Reconstruction
(theoretically concerned that all nations observe the Mosaic legislation) and
much more specific about the legislation that it believes is to be observed.
Theonomy does not wish merely a return to a biblical ethic, or a Judeo-Christian
ethic, but to the ethic of the Sinai covenant.
It
is not my purpose to discuss or evaluate Christian Reconstructionism here. It is
a broad, many-faced movement, and is beyond the scope of my concern. My purpose
is to discuss that much narrower program, adopted indeed by many
Reconstructionists, ordinarily called Theonomy, as I have described it. I am not
arguing that it is wrong not to distinguish them, nor am I arguing that my label
or description is the only useful one; I am merely trying to clarify the scope
of my intentions.
3.
Distinguishing Details from the Basic Program
A
further introductory clarification is in order. It is also not my purpose to
examine in detail the particular recommendations for legislation, nor the
particular exegetical conclusions of the various Theonomists. Those varying
particulars are worthy of separate analysis and discussion, but my purpose is
much more limited: to examine the hermeneutic governing the entire process. I am
evaluating the engine, not the entire train. Further, I am aware that many who
consider themselves Theonomists disagree about aspects of that hermeneutical
program, and so it is not my purpose to “tar” every self-proclaimed
Theonomist with the same brush. Individuals should be evaluated individually,
and those who do not embrace the hermeneutic that I here describe are free of
the critique.
Despite
the variety on particulars, however, there can be little doubt that the
clearest, most deliberate attempt to describe and defend Theonomy is contained
in Gregory L. Bahnsen’s Theonomy in Christian Ethics.1
It is my purpose to employ this volume as the most reliable indicator of what
Theonomy is. Those who embrace a particular variation differing from Bahnsen’s
are thus free of the critique here developed, at least potentially.
4.
Dividing the Question
It
will also be my purpose to critique Theonomy in several ways, in terms of the
varying arguments by which it is promoted. Theonomy does not stand on a single
leg, but on several. Those individuals who already reject one or two of those
legs may find it convenient to skip my discussion of those matters, and go on to
the places where I discuss other aspects.
I
will not attempt here a refutation of that particular leg of Theonomy known as
postmillennialism. Many others have very ably discussed that matter, and the
reader is encouraged to read Geerhardus Vos, Richard B. Gaffin, Jr., Herman
Ridderbos, O. Palmer Robertson, Meredith G. Kline,2
and others who have written in this area. An additional reason for my not
evaluating postmillennialism here is that there are non-Theonomic
postmillennialists. While Theonomy is more attractive to a postmillennialist
than to anyone else, one can be a postmillennialist without agreeing with
Theonomy.
The
following “legs” of the Theonomic stool will be discussed here: the argument
from necessity; the Theonomic dependence upon and understanding of Matt
5:17–21; the Theonomic understanding of covenant theology.
5.
Giving Credit Where Credit Is Due
As
a final introductory comment, I would like to make clear that what follows is
profoundly indebted to insights first raised by others. It is not my intention
to advance exclusively new arguments against Theonomy, but rather, to gather in
one place a brief taxonomy of the major arguments. I have been profoundly helped
by others, and much of what follows was already expressed or at least germinal
in the writings of others. Especially to be acknowledged, in no particular
order, are Meredith G. Kline, Vern S. Poythress, Paul D. Fowler, and Richard B.
Gaffin, Jr.3
At the same time, none of these individuals should be held responsible for
whatever is untrue, unclear, or unhelpful in what follows.
II.
Specific Arguments
1.
The Argument from Necessity
To
my knowledge, Bahnsen’s Theonomy in Christian Ethics does not depend in
any particular measure on this argument. Yet, it is my observation from
conversations with Theonomists that many others rely heavily on this argument.
Indeed, many individuals seem to embrace Theonomy because of their conviction
that Theonomy, or something like it, is necessary. The argument from necessity
is essentially this: we need to know how to function in the civil arena, and
therefore the Word of God must provide us with such instruction. This leads
quickly to embracing the Mosaic legislation for such guidance, since all parties
agree that the only place where statecraft of any sort is comprehensively
recorded in the Scriptures is in the Sinai legislation.
Ordinarily,
in any debated arena, the argument from necessity is fallacious, and evidently
so from a theistic framework. The nature of the curse on the human race
subsequent to the Fall has left us in a circumstance of having many pains and
unfulfilled desires. Often these desires are confused with “needs,” and we
believe our needs must be met, at least potentially, somewhere. However, a
Christian theist recognizes both that there is a distinction between desires and
needs, and that there will always be more desires than solutions to them, at
least prior to the glorified state.
Where
does the Bible address other matters, such as statecraft, science, or medicine?
Does the Bible contain a cure for cancer? Does it contain a solution to the
long-standing debate between engineers and mathematicians regarding the
stability of suspension bridges? And if it does not, why is statecraft different
from these areas? Is a well-run state more necessary than efficient
agriculture? Is a well-run state more necessary than good medicine? If
not, why do we expect biblical directives here and not elsewhere? Are we not
obliged, as God’s creatures, to serve him in all aspects of life? Are we not
obliged, for instance, as Christian practitioners of medicine, to bring glory to
God in all that we do? And yet, we evidently do not have a comprehensive or
particular directive in Scripture for how to serve God in the field of
medicine. If the Theonomic plea from necessity is valid in the field of
statecraft, then someone should indicate either that it is also valid in other
fields, or that statecraft is a different field of human endeavor, subject to
special considerations.
In
fact, it is my judgment that natural revelation is a sufficient guide in each of
these areas. In the field of natural revelation, the tools for understanding our
duty are different than in the field of special revelation. In studying special
revelation, we learn Hebrew and Greek, ancient history and culture, etc. In
studying natural revelation, we learn to weigh, measure, test, etc. Put most
plainly, natural revelation is studied by observation, and by trial-and-error.
In
the field of medicine, for instance, we develop instruments which assist us in
our ability to observe: more powerful microscopes, CAT-scan machines, etc. When
we are able to observe accurately the physical realities, we then propose
theories for dealing with them, and we test those theories by trial-and-error.
It is not different in the field of statecraft. We observe human nature, and
especially human nature in society (sociology, anthropology, political science,
psychology and social psychology, history). From our observations, we propose
theories, and test them by trial-and-error (or, by evaluating how such theories
worked, when and if they have been tested in other societies).
If
we could not develop and refine statecraft by this method, then how can we
account for the fact that many governments have proceeded, with varying degrees
of success, by this method? Further, by what method did the Roman government
proceed in Paul’s day, and could it have been responsible for Paul to urge
obedience to such authorities if he were convinced that such authorities were
fundamentally wrong? Indeed, for all the admitted errors of the Roman
government, Paul’s argument for submitting to them is not merely that the
Roman government existed by God’s providential appointment, but by the
additional argument that the Roman civil authority, at least in a general way,
was indeed fulfilling the divine mandate to punish the wicked (Romans 13).
Many
Theonomists appear to have developed a novel, and erroneous, understanding of
the sufficiency of Scripture. They imply that Scripture is a sufficient guide
for the various departments of life, in all their specificity. In fact, the
Reformational doctrine of the sufficiency of Scripture is a highly nuanced and
sophisticated doctrine.
The
Reformational doctrine of the sufficiency of Scripture does not mean that the
Scriptures are sufficient to answer all of our questions. Rather, the doctrine
means that the Scriptures are a sufficient guide to our communion with God, a
guide to faith and life in the religious sense. WCF 1.6: “The whole
counsel of God concerning all things necessary for his own glory, man’s
salvation, faith and life, is either expressly set down in Scripture, or by good
and necessary consequence may be deduced from Scripture.”
Theonomists
often argue that it is “necessary for…man’s…life” that humans have
revealed directives for statecraft. If this argument were valid, however, why
would it not be equally (or more) valid to argue that it is “necessary
for…man’s…life” that humans have revealed directives for medicine? Is it
not the case when our loved ones die that the Scriptures have not been, in their
medicinal instructions, sufficient in providing what is “necessary
for…man’s…life”? Is it not the case, when a suspension bridge collapses
due to no construction failure, that the Scriptures have evidently not provided
adequate instruction in the field of design?
I
have never received an answer to this line of questioning from any of the
Theonomists with whom I have conversed. I do not think it likely that I will.
Yet I think the line of questioning not only deserves an answer, I also think it
reveals something about Theonomy’s agenda. For Theonomists, statecraft is
simply more important than medicine, science, engineering, etc. Possibly due to
their postmillennialism, possibly due to their (understandable) heartbreak over
the decline of the West, and possibly due to other, less tangible factors, they
have simply placed statecraft higher on their agenda than it is on other
people’s agenda. Yet they have not demonstrated why the solution to
statecraft is more pressing than the solution to these other matters.
2.
The Theonomic Dependence upon and Misunderstanding of Matt 5:17-21
(1)
The role of Matt 5:17–21 in the Theonomic hermeneutic. Paul Fowler
correctly observed that Bahnsen’s entire case for his approach to the
“abiding validity of the law in exhaustive detail” was based upon his
understanding of Matt 5:17–21.4
Fowler pointed out how frequently this passage is cited in Theonomy in
Christian Ethics as proof of the observation. Even the casual reader of
Bahnsen’s treatise recognizes that Matt 5:17–21 is cited again and again.
Thus, if Bahnsen cannot make his case from this text, his case is not made.
We
might go further and suggest that Bahnsen not only found in this passage a
convenient defense of his hermeneutic, but that he could have found such a
defense only here. The rest of the NT is so entirely silent on the issue, that
it was necessary to Theonomy’s case to establish itself on the basis of this
text. Other NT passages provide counter-evidence. The sweeping statement
(covenantally conditioned) in Heb 7:12 that where the priesthood changes,
necessarily the law must change;5 Paul’s general
statement that believers are “not under the law”;6
Paul’s discussing the matter of civil obedience without any reference to the
Sinai legislation (Romans 13); and the evident suspending of the ceremonial
legislation by the Jerusalem Council, Paul, and the author of Hebrews are
matters which point compellingly away from Bahnsen’s suggestion that the Sinai
legislation is abidingly valid in exhaustive detail.
(2)
The Theonomic understanding of Matt 5:17–21. In four specific ways,
Bahnsen’s treatment of Matt 5:17ff. is deficient.7
First, he “washes out” the prophetic half of the “law and the prophets,”
effectively leaving only the “law” under consideration. Second, he
misunderstands the use of πληρόω in the passage to
mean “ratify” rather than “fulfill.” Third, if he proves his thesis
regarding “exhaustive detail” he proves too much, and would be required to
conclude that the Jerusalem Council and the apostle Paul should be called least
in the kingdom of heaven. Fourth, he fails to appreciate the genuinely temporal
character of the parallel temporal clauses, “until heaven and earth pass
away,” and “until all things come to pass.”
“Law
and prophets” is a somewhat difficult expression in the Scriptures, and we do
not intend to suggest that its precise meaning is self-evident. There are places
where it could be a reference to the OT Scriptures in their comprehensive scope
(Luke 24:44; Acts 24:14; Acts 28:23). The expression could refer to an entire
revelatory era in the history of redemption (Matt 11:13: “For all the prophets
and the law prophesied until John came”). The expression might even be a
reference to the written constitutional document of the Sinai covenant (Matt
7:12: “In everything do to others as you would have them do to you; for this
is the law and the prophets”; 22:40: “On these two commandments hang all the
law and the prophets”). But it is very unlikely that “law and prophets”
can be taken as a reference exclusively, or even primarily, to the “ethical
stipulations contained in the canon of the entire Older Testament.”8
Even in the two texts where the expression appears to focus on the ethical
requirements of that administration, it is both the law and the prophetic
administration of that law which are referred to.
The
significance of this observation is profound in its consequences for exegesis.
Biblically, “law and prophets” are conjoined. They are together in their
function, and the prophets are in fact executors of the Sinai covenant. Their
anticipation of Messiah’s arrival is part of their declaration of judgment on
Israel for her unfaithfulness to the covenant, because only the Messiah will be
able to deliver from the curses of the Sinai administration. From a biblical
perspective, if the Sinai legislation remains, then the prophetic office of
preparing for the Messiah’s arrival remains also.
The
most daring dimension of Bahnsen’s interpretation of Matt 5:17ff. is his
argument that πληρω$σαι
should be interpreted to mean “ratify” rather than “fulfill.” This
interpretation is consistent with his interpreting the prophets out of the
“law and the prophets,” yet it is erroneous nonetheless.
His
argument follows sound lexicographical considerations, but reaches erroneous
conclusions, because some of the alternatives are not considered. Bahnsen is
correct in attempting to interpret πληρω$σαι
as functioning antithetically in this passage to
καταλυ$σαι.
This is not only required by the general context, but by the fact that “law
and prophets” is the direct object of each of the two verbs in question. He
then argues that it would not make sense to speak of “fulfilling” the law,
but that it would make sense to speak of “ratifying” the law. He is
certainly right that this is plausible. However, this meaning of
πληρω$σαι would not make much sense of the prophetic dimension
of the equation; how would Jesus be “ratifying” the prophets? It would be
better to find an understanding of both verbs, πληρω$σαι and καταλυ$σαι,
which makes sense of both of the direct objects.
If
we take the “law and prophets” together as a reference to the Sinai
covenant, or the era in which God’s people are governed thereby, then it makes
sense to understand Jesus to be saying that he has not come (at least in his
humiliated state) to abolish that covenantal administration, but to bring it to
its conclusion. Since the other ²$λθον-statements
of Jesus are routinely understood as being a reference to his humiliated state
(his earthly ministry prior to his resurrection and ascension), there is also no
conflict between such a statement and the reality that later he does terminate
the one covenant administration and inaugurate a new one.
As
Vern Poythress has demonstrated,9
such a rendering is also much more consistent with the ordinary understanding of
πληρω$σαι
in contexts where the direct object is prophetic. Indeed, there is no evidence
that the prophets were ever thought of as legislating, but there is evidence,
within Matthew’s Gospel, that the law was conceived of as prophesying: “For
all the prophets and the law prophesied until John” (11:13).
Thus,
there is a way of interpreting πληρω$σαι
in this text which is consistent with both “law” and “prophets,” which
does not require a de facto “washing out” of the one or the other.
This way of understanding the verb is consistent with how the verb is regularly
related to “prophets”; it is consistent with Matt 11:13; and it is
consistent with the portrait of Christ elsewhere in the NT as functioning within
the Sinai covenant until he established the new by his death and resurrection,
and therefore requiring his disciples to obey the Mosaic law until the New
Covenant was inaugurated (Matt 23:2–3: “The scribes and the Pharisees sit on
Moses’ seat; therefore, do whatever they teach you and follow it”).
Bahnsen
attempts to establish a thesis that Jesus, in Matthew 5, reiterates for all time
the validity of the entire Mosaic law, not merely the “moral” law, and that
he does so “in exhaustive detail.” Such an interpretation, if correct, would
necessarily either condemn Paul and the other apostles or destroy Theonomy. Paul
not only relaxes one, but several of the Mosaic laws, and not merely the
“least,” but several of the major laws, to wit, circumcision, the Jewish
calendar, and the dietary laws.
Bahnsen’s
only escape from such a conundrum is to argue that Paul does not actually break
these laws, but applies them differently to another covenantal context. This
consideration, while removing the hermeneutic from the hotseat, destroys the
very thing which the hermeneutic wishes to accomplish. If the law requiring a
bloody rite (circumcision) can be fulfilled by a non-bloody rite (baptism), then
where would Bahnsen’s arguments for capital punishment necessarily go? Would
we wash criminals today who commit capital crimes? If we would not, then
why not? If we fulfill the requirement of not eating with Gentiles by eating
with Gentiles, then do we fulfill the requirement of not murdering by murdering?
If we fulfill the requirement of eating a feast on the day of atonement by not
eating a feast on the day of atonement, then do we fulfill other mosaic laws by
not doing them? If this were so, what would be left of Theonomy? How could the
mosaic law possibly function as a guide for civil governments today, if the
mosaic laws could be properly applied by not following them?
It
would actually be the better of the two options for Bahnsen simply to conclude
that Paul, the Jerusalem Council, and the author of Hebrews (and, as the
inspirer of their words, the Holy Spirit) will share the honors as “least in
the kingdom of heaven.” This would still preserve the hermeneutic to provide
direction for civil governments today, and would only have the difficulty of
requiring a blanket condemnation of those whom Jesus appointed to be the
foundation of the church.
Of
course, we believe the paint on the bottom of Bahnsen’s shoes was
self-applied, as soon as he left the corner into which he had painted himself.
Had the “law and prophets” been correctly understood as a reference to the
entire revelation within the Sinai administration, Jesus’ intention would have
been clear: he would not abrogate any of the requirements or promises of that
covenant administration until he had brought it to its fulfillment and had
established a new covenant.
The
strongest apparent exegetical case for Bahnsen’s viewpoint resides in his
taking the two temporal clauses as metaphors which, when negated, mean
“never.”10
Thus, the passage would be interpreted as teaching that all of the requirements
of the Sinai administration continue forever. However, if these two temporal
clauses can be demonstrated to be non-metaphors, and actual temporal clauses,
then all that can be proven by Matthew 5 is that the Mosaic covenant, both in
its prophetic and legal aspects, abides temporarily, until God changes it by
causing heaven and earth to pass away, and by bringing “all things” to pass.
Matt
24:34–35 demonstrates that the temporal clauses of Matt 5:17ff. are genuine
temporal clauses: “Truly I tell you, this generation will not pass away until
all these things have taken place [ªως
ν πάντα
γένηται]. Heaven and earth will pass away [Ò
οÛρανÎς
κα º
γη$
παρελεύσεται], but
my words will not pass away.” Note that the two expressions in Matthew 5 that
appear to teach that not a jot or tittle will ever pass away need not be
understood in such a way. “All things” will come to pass, or take
place, and heaven and earth will pass away.
True,
within a modern cosmology, it is difficult to believe that “heaven and
earth” can pass away. It is thus not farfetched for Bahnsen to say regarding
this verse that “the law will remain valid at least as long as the physical
universe lasts.”11
But within a biblical cosmology, it not only can happen, but already did
happen once before, and will happen again: “They deliberately ignore this
fact, that by the word of God heavens existed long ago and an earth
was formed out of water and by means of water, through which the world of that
time was deluged with water and perished [πώλετο]. But by the same word the present
heavens and earth [Ò
δ¥ νυ$ν
οÛρανοÂ
κα º
γη$] have been reserved for fire, being kept until the day of judgment and
destruction [κρίσεως καÂ
πωλείας] of the godless” (2 Pet 3:5–7).
“Heaven and earth,” biblically, refer to the created order in terms of its
created purpose, to serve God. The “destruction” or “passing away” of
heaven and earth is also then spoken of when God judges its inhabitants.
Cosmologically, the heaven and earth were not annihilated in the flood.
Covenantally, however, the inhabitants thereof were judged by God, and the
judgment was spoken of as perishing or“destruction.”12
The
only remaining issue, then, is when such judgment/destruction of the
heavens and the earth will take place. Within a NT eschatology, I believe there
is a sense in which this took place with the death of Jesus, and another sense
in which it will take place at his return. At Christ’s death, God’s judgment
came upon the Representative of those under God’s wrath; at his return it will
come upon those who are not under the Mediator’s representation. Thus, Matthew
records that, at the crucifixion, darkness came upon “the whole earth” (σκότος
¦γένετο ¦πÂ
πα$σαν
τ¬ν γη$ν,
27:45), even though earlier the darkening of the sun was prophesied to be that
which would attend the return of Christ to judge (Ò »λιος
σκοτισθήσεται,
24:29). In each case, the portents in the heavens and earth were symbols of
divine judgment. Similarly, signs elsewhere associated with the return of Christ
to raise the dead were also provisionally fulfilled at his death: “Then Jesus
cried again with a loud voice and breathed his last. At that moment the curtain
of the temple was torn in two, from top to bottom. The earth shook, and the
rocks were split. The tombs also were opened, and many bodies of the saints who
had fallen asleep were raised. After his resurrection they came out of the tombs
and entered the holy city and appeared to many” (Matt 27:50–53).
For
our purposes, then, the expressions in Matt 5:17ff. which suggest that the
“law and prophets” will never pass away, nor any part thereof, must be
understood as in fact genuine temporal expressions, indicating that they will
not pass away until all the matters prophetically anticipated come to
pass, as D. A. Carson and others have argued.13
From both an OT and a gospel perspective, OT prophecies are seen as coming to
fulfillment at a single moment, which “moment” the remainder of the NT
writings divide into two. Only the apostolic, post-resurrection instruction
enables us, with any confidence, to determine which aspects are fulfilled in the
first coming of the Messiah, and which in his second coming. And such
instruction plainly indicates that many of the “jots and tittles,” not the
least of which are circumcision, the calendar, and the dietary code, have indeed
passed away.
3.
The Theonomic Understanding of Covenant Theology
(1)
Historical-theological considerations. Not surprisingly, there has not
been complete unanimity in understanding the relations among the various
covenantal administrations in the Bible, even among those who consider
themselves “covenant theologians.” It is not surprising, because developing
a theology of the covenants, or a biblical theology (in the Vosian sense), is
one of the most synthetic and comprehensive of the theological disciplines. For
centuries, there has been discussion about how best to describe the similarities
and dissimilarities between the various biblical covenants and the various
redemptive epochs. Although I embrace one of those viewpoints, what follows is
designed more to set the discussion of Theonomy within a history-of-doctrine
framework, than to promote the viewpoint I hold.
Prior
to the Westminster Assembly’s meeting, a fairly substantial amount of work had
been done discussing the relations between the various biblical covenants.14
Samuel Bolton provided a fairly thorough list of options which were present in
his day, in a volume first published while the assembly was still in process (The
True Bounds of Christian Freedom, 1645). Interestingly, as early as the
seventeenth century, the Sinai covenant was considered to be perhaps the most
difficult covenant administration for covenant theologians to come to terms
with. According to Bolton, the difficulty was due to the way that covenant
theology attempted to distinguish the covenants made with the two Adams from all
other covenants. Having correctly determined that these covenants, made with two
representative individuals who were sinless at the time of the administration,
were necessarily different from other covenants, covenant theology then went on
to distinguish these from other covenants, ordinarily by applying the label
“covenant of works” to the Adamic covenants, and “covenant of grace” to
the others. In and of itself, this was not too great a problem, but it became a
problem when discussing the Sinai administration, which apparently all conceded
had both legal and gracious aspects.
Bolton
described four approaches to dealing with this situation. (1) Those who
recognized a covenant of nature, a covenant of grace, and a covenant mixed with
nature and grace. (2) Those who recognized a foedus natura made with man
before the Fall, a foedus promissi made with Adam after the Fall, and a foedus
operi, a covenant of works made with the Jews at Sinai. (3) Those who
recognized a foedus natura made with man before the Fall, a foedus
gratiae (a covenant of grace made with us in Christ), and a foedus
subserviens (subservient covenant) made with the Jews at Sinai. (4) Those
who never did recognize but two covenants, one of works before the Fall and one
of grace after, “Yet…this covenant of grace was dispensed to the Jews in
such a legal manner that it seems to be nothing else but the repetition of the
covenant of works.”15
Interestingly,
each of the four views revealed a tension between the desire to recognize two
covenants (those made with the sinless mediators and those made with sinners)
and the desire to recognize three covenants (Bolton, for what it’s worth,
adopted the third view, above). Further, the tension was caused by the Sinai
covenant’s having similarities both to the covenant of works/nature and to the
covenant of promise/grace.
Charles
Hodge’s view in the nineteenth century reflected the same tension reflected in
the seventeenth century in understanding biblical covenants. Especially
important for our purposes was Hodge’s candid recognition that Sinai was
indeed difficult to describe, precisely because it continued the covenant of
grace while also retaining (for typological reasons) a “legal” element:
Besides
this evangelical character which unquestionably belongs to the Mosaic covenant,
it is presented in two other aspects in the Word of God. First, it was a
national covenant with the Hebrew people. In this view the parties were God and
the people of Israel; the promise was national security and prosperity; the
condition was the obedience of the people as a nation to the Mosaic law; and the
mediator was Moses. In this aspect it was a legal covenant. It said, “Do this
and live.”16
It
should be noted, however, that while there was widespread willingness to concede
a legal dimension to the Sinai administration, there were also individuals
unwilling to speak in this manner. Perhaps most prominent among these voices, in
the nineteenth century, was that of Robert Lewis Dabney.
Coming
now to the last stage of the old dispensation, the Covenant of Sinai, we find
several marked and impressive additions to the former revelations. But they will
all be found rather developments of existing features of the gospel, than new
elements.
The Covenant of Sinai
has seemed to many to wear such an aspect of legality, that they have supposed
themselves constrained to regard it as a species of Covenant of Works…. This
is untenable; because it is inconsistent with God’s spiritual and unchangeable
character, and with His honour.17
Dabney’s
disagreement was partially due to a misunderstanding. Dabney apparently believed
that a covenant was either gracious or legal. Believing this, and
rightly recognizing that there were true saints under the Sinai administration,
who would profit from the gracious atoning work of Christ, Dabney could not
describe such an administration as “legal.” What he appears to have
misunderstood is that the legal dimension recognized by many at Sinai was only one
dimension. That is, other orthodox theologians had not argued that the Sinai
administration was exclusively, or even primarily, legal; they had argued that
there was a legal dimension, related to the inheritance of the land of Canaan.
Dabney’s
disagreement was also due, however, to a genuine error on his part, one which
would not remain confined to him. Note that Dabney considered it “untenable”
for Sinai to be legal, because this would be “inconsistent with God’s
spiritual and unchangeable character.” For Dabney, an unchangeable character
is not capable, apparently, of revealing “new elements” to subsequent
covenant-administrations, but only of revealing “developments of existing
features.” For Dabney, covenants (and laws) are reflections of the character
of the one establishing the covenants (and laws) and thus are no more changeable
than the character of the one so establishing them. Dabney fell philosophically
in the Western tradition of natural law, mediated to him most directly through
Scottish Common Sense philosophy. This is even clearer in his discussion of law
than in his discussion of covenants:
These
(moral distinctions) are intrinsic in that class of acts. They are not
instituted solely by the positive will of God, but are enjoined by that will
because His infinite mind saw them to be intrinsic and eternal. In a word:
Duties are not obligatory and right solely because God has commanded them; but
He has commanded them because they are right…. Just so; it is admitted that
the basis of the moral distinction is a priori to all volition of God.18
Space
does not permit a refutation of this brand of natural law theory here, though
any theist can quickly perceive the direction such a refutation would take.19
Rather, our purpose is to indicate that some covenant theologians were resistant
to the notion of “new elements” entering various covenant administrations,
and that they did so because of certain philosophical commitments which had
long-standing roots in the West.
With
the arrival of dispensationalism an interesting thing happened to covenant
theology, at least in some circles. Properly alarmed over the almost total
discontinuity alleged to exist between the Sinai administration and the New
Covenant by dispensationalists, covenant theologians became shy about the
“works” dimension of the Sinai covenant, which had been candidly (though not
unanimously) conceded within covenant theology before. Rightly reacting to the
dispensational (and incipiently Arminian) denial of a unified purpose of
redemption, covenant theologians became at times reactionary about the
suggestion of any differences among the covenant administrations, as
though admitting such differences would cause one to slide down the slippery
slope toward dispensationalism. Perhaps the most celebrated example has been the
tendency to perceive Meredith G. Kline’s views as unusual or novel, when they
are in fact virtually identical (in broad stroke) with the views discussed by
Bolton in the early 1640s. It is not my intention to explicate or defend
Kline’s views here, but to remind that his views are not at all novel; they
are over 350 years old. His views have been perceived as unusual in the
context of a generation in full reaction against dispensationalism.
One
of the interesting twists of the twentieth century (at least from a
seventeenth-century perspective) would be the covenant views of John Murray,
especially as those views are expressed in his pamphlet, The Covenant of
Grace. Murray recognized that his views on the covenant of grace were
intentionally novel: “It appears to me that the covenant theology…needs
recasting.”20
It is not odd that the twentieth century would find it necessary to recast
earlier theology, of course. But what is interesting is the particular nature of
Murray’s recasting. The seventeenth century found a two-covenant approach
difficult, so difficult that it either found itself proposing a three-covenant
approach or a two-covenant approach with a “legal” administration as a
subset of the second (sort of a two-and-a-half covenant view). Murray’s
recasting, however, became effectively mono-covenantal, as he proposed a view
which perceived all biblical covenants as essentially similar. He did this in
two ways. First, he omitted discussion of the Adamic administration from the
pamphlet,21
thereby reducing the amount of difference among covenant administrations by
discussing only the post-Fall covenants (which, of course, are much more similar
one to another than they are to the covenants with the two Adams). Second, he
was particularly resistant to recognizing any structural distinction between the
promissory Abrahamic covenant and the (at least partially) “legal” Sinai
covenant. He spent very little space distinguishing the Abrahamic from the Sinai
covenant, and in fact recognized only a difference of emphasis there.22
This made his view different from any of the four options mentioned by Bolton.
Now
is not the time to enter into a full evaluation of Murray’s “recasting,”
though I think covenant theology was better off without it. To Murray’s
credit, he very honestly acknowledged the novelty of aspects of his views, and
that he was intending to recast what was, to him, a deficient system. The point
here is merely to indicate that, whether in conscious reaction to
dispensationalism or not, Murray promoted a view which was intentionally quite
different from that of some of the covenant theologians of earlier generations,23
and one of the differences resided in acknowledging fewer areas of covenantal
discontinuity than had been previously recognized within covenant theology.24
It
may not be merely coincidental, then, that many of the more ardent proponents of
Theonomy are influenced by the same tradition that influenced (and possibly
culminated in) John Murray. If Dabney, Murray, et al. were uncomfortable
recognizing fundamental differences in the stipulations of the Mosaic covenant
and other biblical covenants, it would not be surprising if those influenced by
them would be uncomfortable recognizing fundamental differences in the legislation
within the various covenants. The majority of American Presbyterians have always
differed with the majority of Scottish Presbyterians over the civil magistrate,
and this difference itself reflects a deeper (though often implicit more than
explicit) difference over the Israelite theocracy. Was that theocracy a model
for all civil government, or was it a type of the eschatological kingdom?25 Any good “crown and
covenant” Scottish Presbyterian (and Murray was a good one) tends to answer
this differently than a good American Presbyterian. If space permitted, we would
attempt to demonstrate that this difference itself rests upon philosophical
presuppositions. The Scottish Common Sense interpretation of natural law theory
conceives the universe as having an unchanging order inherent within it, and
thus tends to view anything which is “new”
as merely a clearer understanding of what was always incipiently present.
Individuals influenced by this tradition tend to see later biblical covenants
merely as organic developments of what was incipient in earlier covenants.26
(2)
Covenant theology in Theonomy. Whether due to the direct influence of
Dabney and Murray or not, it is without doubt that Theonomy’s approach to
biblical covenants tends toward mono-covenantalism. What is distinctive about
Theonomy is its resistance to recognizing discontinuity in the legislation of
the various covenants.
What’s
in a word? Well, in this case, plenty. Theonomy’s resistance to recognizing
covenantal distinctions as they are represented in Scripture goes even so far as
to change conventional Christian nomenclature. Throughout Theonomy in
Christian Ethics, Bahnsen promotes the neologistic “older covenant” and
“newer covenant.” Jeremiah was most assuredly not looking forward to a
“newer” edition of the “older covenant”; he anticipated a “new
covenant…not like the covenant I made with their fathers” (Jer
31:31–32). Jesus, similarly, did not institute, by his sacrifice, merely a
“newer” covenant. He did not refer to the cup as a “newer” covenant, but
as a “new” covenant, and his apostles similarly considered themselves
“ministers of a new covenant” (2 Corinthians 3). The point is not merely
terminological, but conceptual. The new covenant is not merely different in
comparative degree from the Sinai covenant; it is also different in
qualitative kind from that covenant; it is, at least in some respects,
“not like” the covenant God made with the ancestors when he took them out of
Egypt.
If
there is a hermeneutical commitment evident in Theonomy (despite the genuine
differences on many particular exegetical points within Theonomy) it is the
belief that the Sinai legislation, even in its judicial dimensions, is
legislation which is well-suited for, and intended to be observed by, all
nations and peoples. Now plainly, the duties of a given covenant are only
obligatory on those who are parties to the covenant. For Theonomy, however, all
peoples in all times are obliged to these duties, unless there is some
instruction somewhere else in Scripture exempting particular peoples from
particular duties. The Theonomic approach, then, abstracts the legislation from
its covenantal context. Apparently, for Theonomy, a covenant really was made at
Sinai, but the legislation was a peripheral, incidental dimension of the
covenant itself; or, a covenant was really made at Sinai, and the covenant
itself continues until the return of Christ.
One
of the most profound ironies has been the failure of covenant theologians (with
some exceptions) to critique Theonomy on this point. One would think that
covenant theologians would have some idea of what a covenant is. Do covenants
have parties, or do they not? Do covenants have obligations and sanctions, or do
they not? If a covenant has parties, how is it that non-parties are obliged to
its duties? How could the Gentiles, described by the apostle Paul as “outside
of the law” (νόμως) possibly be obliged to the law?
How could it possibly be meaningful for Paul to distinguish Jews from Gentiles
because “to them belong…the covenants, the giving of the law” (Rom 9:4),
if the covenant and its laws oblige non-Jews equally with Jews?
Theonomists
are not the first to abstract legislation from the Sinai covenant. The
Westminster Assembly appears to have done it beforehand, though on a much
smaller scale and in a more ambiguous manner. The divines at Westminster appear
to have abstracted the decalogue from the Sinai covenant, and to have understood
the ten words as timeless and, if you will, “covenant-less.” This is
revealed in the Westminster Confession of Faith 19.1-2 (emphasis mine):
God
gave to Adam a law, as a covenant of works, by which he bound him and all his
posterity to personal, entire, exact, and perpetual obedience, promised life
upon the fulfilling, and threatened death upon the breach of it, and endued him
with power and ability to keep it. This law, after his fall, continued to
be a perfect rule of righteousness; and, as such, was delivered by God upon
Mount Sinai, in ten commandments, and written in two tables: the four first
commandments containing our duty towards God; and the other six, our duty to
man. [WCF 19.2, emphasis mine]
The
assembly asserted that God gave the ten commandments (or the equivalent thereof)
to Adam, and then gave the same law to Moses. This assertion then, if
unchallenged, permits the decalogue to be perceived as a timeless,
“covenant-less” expression of God’s moral will.
This
assertion is not only completely without any biblical evidence, but it is an
assertion contrary to some of the evidence in Scripture, most notably Rom 5:13,
“sin was indeed in the world before the law.” Note that the assembly places
the law “in the garden”; Paul places it outside of the garden, after
sin entered the world. The evidence becomes even greater when we recognize
throughout the Scriptures the close relation between the ten commandments and
the Sinai covenant. Biblically, far from being “abstractable” from that
covenant administration, the ten commandments are the heart thereof. The
biblical authors can speak, at least by synecdoche, of the Sinai covenant as being
the ten commandments. Further, the “tablets” engraved at Sinai are often
qualified as the tablets “of the covenant,” and this covenant is stated to
have not been made with others prior to that generation.27
Deut
4:13: He declared to you his covenant, which he charged you to observe, that
is, the ten commandments; and he wrote them on two stone tablets.
Exod
31:18: When God finished speaking with Moses on Mount Sinai, he gave him the two
tablets of the covenant, tablets of stone, written with the finger of God.
Deut
9:9, 11: When I went up the mountain to receive the stone tablets, the tablets
of the covenant that the LORD made with you, I remained on the mountain
forty days and forty nights; I neither ate bread nor drank water….
At
the end of forty days and forty nights the LORD gave me the two stone
tablets, the tablets of the covenant.
Exod
34:27–29: The LORD said to Moses: Write these words; in accordance with these
words I have made a covenant with you and with Israel. He was there with the
LORD forty days and forty nights; he neither ate bread nor drank water. And he
wrote on the tablets the words of the covenant, the ten commandments.
Moses came down from Mount Sinai. As he came down from the mountain with the two
tablets of the covenant in his hand, Moses did not know that the skin of his
face shone because he had been talking with God.
Deut
5:2–3: The LORD our God made a covenant with us at Horeb. Not with our
ancestors did the LORD make this covenant, but with us, who are all of us
here alive today.
Although
the assembly appears to have contributed to misunderstandings of the decalogue
in subsequent generations, it must be remembered that their purpose was
catechetical, not biblical-theological. Their desire to find some location in
which the moral will of God was “summarily comprehended” was catechetically
proper, despite the misunderstanding of the covenantal role of the decalogue
which may have resulted therefrom. Further, it must be noted that the assembly
“limited” the damage done, by abstracting only the decalogue. In WCF
19.3-4, the assembly indicated that there were other aspects of the Sinai
legislation (which they called “ceremonial” and “judicial”) that were
covenantally conditioned.
Despite
these qualifications, it must be admitted that the work of the assembly
established the precedent of abstracting covenantal duties from the covenant in
which they were given. This precedent, combined with the reactionary response to
the errors of dispensationalism, created soil in the twentieth century which
virtually guaranteed that Theonomy, or something like it, would take root.
Theonomy
follows the a-covenantal hermeneutic of the Westminster Assembly, yet without
the qualifications or limitations of WCF 19:4: “To them also, as a body
politic, he gave sundry judicial laws, which expired together with the state of
that people; not obliging any other now, further than the general equity thereof
may require.” Theonomy tends to abstract all of the Sinai legislation
from its covenantal setting. While some Theonomists borrow the confessional
language of “general equity,” they rarely employ it with the four
confessional qualifications, namely, the recognition that those in covenant with
God at Sinai were a “body politic” (unlike the New Covenant community); that
those laws “expired together with the state of that people”; that such are
“not obliging any other now”; and that the general equity only may
require that some of that body of legislation would be equitable generally to
other nations.
Thus,
Theonomy follows the assembly in abstracting the decalogue from the covenant
administration in which it is given, and of which it is the essential feature;
it does not follow the assembly, however, in abstracting the other legislation
therefrom. Theonomy agrees with the assembly where I do not; I agree with the
assembly where Theonomy does not. On the particular issue at hand, whether the
obligation to the judicial laws of Sinai is universal, I agree with the assembly
and Theonomy does not. However, our confessional tradition has at least opened
the door to a covenant-less understanding of some of the Sinai
legislation, and is now reaping some of the consequences.
Further,
this observation is intended to help explain, in part, Theonomy’s origins.
Theonomy did not appear “out of the blue,” as some may think. Individuals in
our tradition who consider Theonomy to be an outrageous or extreme viewpoint are
only partially correct. It is true that Theonomy denies WCF 19:4, and it
is true that Theonomy is even more extreme than Dabney or Murray in the
resistance to recognizing the distinctive traits of the Sinai covenant. Theonomy
would indeed establish the extreme end of the covenant theology spectrum.
However, Theonomy genuinely shares some of the distinctives embraced by others
within that tradition. It shares the assembly’s abstracting of the decalogue
from the Sinai covenant, and then goes further; it shares the tendency of some
reactionaries to dispensationalism to deny unique features of the Sinai covenant
which earlier generations routinely recognized.
Theonomy,
thus, cannot be accounted for merely on sociological or psychological grounds.
It is not merely a sociological phenomenon, resisting the tide of a
post-Christian culture (though this is undoubtedly an important reason for the
popularity of the movement with some). Nor is it merely a psychological
phenomenon, an uprising of authoritarian personalities (though there is
undoubtedly a measure of truth to this). It is also an intellectual movement, an
extension (albeit extreme) of ideas already germinal in some dimensions of the
Reformed tradition.
Gordon-Conwell
Theological Seminary
S. Hamilton, Massachusetts 01982
1 Theonomy
in Christian Ethics: Expanded Edition with Replies to Critics
(Phillipsburg, NJ: Presbyterian and Reformed, 1984)
2 I
will not attempt here to give exhaustive bibliographies of these
individuals. It is ubiquitous in Vos, Ridderbos, and Kline, of course, and
is evident in Palmer Robertson’s “Is There a Distinctive Future for
Ethnic Israel in Romans 11?” in Perspectives on Evangelical Theology
(ed. K. Kantzer and S. Gundry; Grand Rapids: Baker, 1979) 209-27, and in
Richard B. Gaffin’s “Theonomy and Eschatology: Reflections on
Postmillennialism,” in Theonomy: A Reformed Critique (ed. W. Barker
and R. Godfrey; Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1990) 197-226.
3 All
of Kline’s writings are implicitly germane, but especially his “Comments
on a New-Old Error: A Review of Greg Bahnsen, Theonomy in Christian
Ethics,” WTJ 41 (1978–79) 172–89. Poythress’s
considerations are found in audio form in a series of lectures available
through Westminster Media, and also in his The Shadow of Christ in the
Law of Moses (Nashville, TN: Wolgemuth & Hyatt, 1991), esp. two of
the appendices, “Evaluating Theonomy,” (pp. 311-61), and “Does the
Greek Word PlroÇ Sometimes Mean ‘Confirm’?” (pp. 363-77), and again in his
“Effects of Interpretive Frameworks on the Application of Old Testament
Law,” in Theonomy: A Reformed Critique, 103–23. Paul D.
Fowler’s review (never published but frequently photocopied) of
Bahnsen’s Theonomy is a very helpful work. Gaffin’s influence is
implicit, because of his understanding of NT eschatology generally, as
reflected in his classroom lectures at Westminster Seminary, and in his
previously cited article, “Theonomy and Eschatology.”
4 Unpublished
typescript.
5 Cf. John Owen, Works
of John Owen (24 vols.; London: Johnstone & Hunter, 1850–55)
21.431: “Besides, such was the contexture of the law, and such the
sanction of it, (‘Cursed is every one who continueth not in all things
which are written in the book of the law to do them,’) that if any thing
be taken out of it, if its order be disturbed, if any alteration be made, or
any transgression be dispensed withal, or exempted from the curse, the whole
fabric must of necessity fall unto the ground.” Owen rightly observed that
the stipulations of Sinai could not be abstracted from the sanctions of
Sinai, nor from the priestly atonement of Sinai. All were part of the same
covenantal “contexture” or “fabric.”
6 Following Moo, we
would argue that Paul’s use of νόμος is
ordinarily a reference to the covenant administration made at Sinai, and
that the expression ßπÎ
νόμον is a reference to being a party to that
covenant. Cf. Douglas J. Moo, “ ‘Law,’ ‘Works of the Law,’ and
Legalism in Paul,” WTJ 45 (1983) 80, 88: “What is vital for any
accurate understanding of Paul’s doctrine of law is to realize that Paul
uses nomos most often and most basically of the Mosaic law…. As we
have seen, the Reformers, as most theologians today, use ‘law’ to mean
anything that demands something of us. In this sense, ‘law’ is a basic
factor in all human history; and man is in every age, whether in the OT or
NT, confronted with ‘law.’ What is crucial to recognize is that this is not
the way in which Paul usually uses the term nomos.”
7 The hermeneutical
heart of Bahnsen’s Theonomy in Christian Ethics can be found in
chap. 2, “The Abiding Validity of the Law in Exhaustive Detail,”
39–86. Rather than clutter my manuscript with references to the particular
places in this chapter, I would direct the reader to that chapter in its
entirety as the best place to find a succinct representation of Theonomy’s
hermeneutic.
8
Theonomy, 50,
emphasis his.
9
Poythress, Shadow of
Christ, App. C, pp.
363-77.
10 “Given the
cultural-literary milieu it is quite likely that this phrase was a graphic
and strong way of saying ‘never’“ (Theonomy, 76).
11 Ibid.
12 Additionally,
it is possible that there is some relation between the inhabitants of
the created order (especially humans, with the God-given duty of cultivating
the created order) and the created order itself, so that the judicial
destruction of the inhabitants of the created order is spoken of as a
destruction of the created order itself. Either understanding is compatible
with the results of this study.
13 From
Sabbath to Lord’s Day (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1982) 77ff. Cf.
also Robert Banks, Jesus and the Law in the Synoptic Tradition
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975), and John P. Meier, Law and
History in Matthew’s Gospel (AnBib 71; Rome: Biblical Institute
Press, 1971).
14 Mark
W. Karlberg has provided a very good overview of various theories of
covenant theology in his “Reformed Interpretation of the Mosaic
Covenant,” WTJ 43 (1980) 1-57.
15 Samuel
Bolton, The True Bounds of Christian Freedom (repr. Edinburgh: Banner
of Truth, 1964) 90.
16 Charles
Hodge, Systematic Theology (repr. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1977)
2.375.
17 Robert
Lewis Dabney, Lectures in Theology (repr. Grand Rapids: Baker, 1985)
452-53.
18 Ibid.,
352.
19 Such
a view as Dabney’s essentially affirms moral law to exist in the universe
apart from the volition of the Creator. Yet who created the universe with
such inherent law, other than the Creator? Who caused such law to inhere in
the universe, if not God? By whose volition was such a universe placed into
existence, if not God’s? Can it possibly be that there are “intrinsic
and eternal” moral laws in the universe, prior to God’s volition, which
God does not establish but only recognizes?
20 John
Murray, The Covenant of Grace (London: Tyndale, 1977) 5, emphasis
mine.
21 Though
Murray discussed this administration thoroughly in his Imputation of Adam’s
Sin (Phillipsburg, NJ: Presbyterian and Reformed, 1959) and in his
paper, “The Adamic Administration,” in The Collected Writings of John
Murray (Edinburgh: Banner of Truth, 1977) 2.47–59.
22 “At
the outset we must remember that the idea of conditional fulfilment is not
something peculiar to the Mosaic covenant. We have been faced quite
poignantly with this very question in connection with the Abrahamic
covenant. And since this feature is there patent, it does not of itself
provide us with any reason for construing the Mosaic covenant in terms
different from those of the Abrahamic” (Murray, The Covenant of Grace,
20). “What needs to be emphasized now is that the Mosaic covenant in
respect of the condition of obedience is not in a different category from
the Abrahamic” (p. 22). Yet earlier, in his description of the Abrahamic
covenant, Murray had said, “The grace dispensed and the relation
established do not wait for the fulfilment of certain conditions on the part
of those to whom the grace is dispensed” (p. 19). Since Murray has already
defined the essence of the covenant to consist in the vital communion
established, and since that particular dimension is sovereignly determined,
he is correct in saying that this dimension does not await the “fulfilment
of certain conditions on the part of those to whom the grace is
dispensed.” The problem is that the inheritance of the land, as a
distinctive feature of the Sinai administration, does depend on the
“fulfilment of certain conditions on the part of those to whom the grace
is dispensed.” Yet when Murray discusses the Sinai covenant, he does not
refer to the conditions of inheriting the land. I would not disagree with
Murray’s saying, for instance, “This fact links the Mosaic very closely
with the Abrahamic and shows that religious relationship on the highest
level is contemplated in both, namely, union and communion with God.” What
I would disagree with is the tendency of Murray to thus discount land
inheritance as a significant feature of the Mosaic administration, and with
it, obedience as the condition of inheritance. Ironically, Murray has
overlooked the eschaton (functionally, anyway) in his description of
“religious relationship on the highest level.” In heaven, which I would
think consists of “religious relation on the highest level,” the place
in which the communion exists is not insignificant. It is a place
free of sin and sinners, free of all of the enemies of God’s people,
“holy” in the highest and most perfect sense. And, in my judgment,
Canaan was a type of that heavenly place. In diminishing the role of
Canaan (and the condition of its inheritance) in the Sinai administration,
Murray has not only failed to describe that covenant administration
adequately, but, ironically, he has disserved his own attempt to describe
accurately the relational dimension of biblical covenants, since one
feature of that relation is that it is exclusively a relation between God
and his people. This exclusive feature is only fully realized in heaven,
when all who are not God’s people are excluded; but this feature is
typified, beautifully, by the land aspect of the Sinai administration.
23 Murray’s
view was not entirely idiosyncratic, however. His resistance to recognizing
the “legal” dimension of the Sinai administration reflects the same
tendency in R. L. Dabney.
24 What
Murray appears to have done is to have defined “covenant” in terms of
the effects of the various covenants, namely, the establishing of
some sort of vital relation between God and his people. This is somewhat
different, and indeed narrower, than the biblical definition of covenant as
inclusive of the particular administration itself, not merely what was
effected thereby. Thus, Murray’s somewhat brief discussion of the
stipulations or requirements of the varying covenants is due to his belief
that such stipulations are not really part of the essence of
covenants. Not surprisingly, then, he perceives little difference between
the Abrahamic and the Sinai covenants, since the effect of each will
be so similar: “I will be their God, and they will be my people.” Paul,
by contrast, describes covenants in terms of their administration and their
stipulations or requirements, and thus contrasts the promissory character of
the Abrahamic and the “works” character of the Sinai covenant in, e.g.,
Galatians 3. The earliest covenant theologians of the sixteenth and
seventeenth centuries appear to have employed the term “covenant” more
as Paul did, including both the stipulations and the effects of varying
covenants, and this is why for them (more than for Murray) the Sinai
administration could be perceived as having a genuinely legal/works
dimension, although not with regard to salvation but with regard to
inheriting and prospering in Canaan.
25 For
evidence that Geerhardus Vos and Cornelius Van Til perceived the theocracy
as a type of the final, eschatological kingdom, see references in my “Van
Til and Theonomic Ethics” in the forthcoming Festschrift for
Meredith G. Kline.
26 In
this regard it may not be insignificant to recall that Charles Hodge studied
in Germany, and was influenced philosophically by the Continent, whereas
Dabney’s philosophical leanings were evidently British. This different
philosophical orientation may very well have accounted for Hodge’s
willingness to speak of the Sinai administration as different in kind from
the Abrahamic, and Dabney’s unwillingness to do the same. Similarly,
Geerhardus Vos, representing the Continent again, recognizes in his biblical
theology not only what he called the “organic principle” (his label for
continuity), but also what he called the “principle of periodicity” (his
label for discontinuity). Cf. Vos’s Biblical Theology (Grand
Rapids: Eerdmans, 1975) 16.
27 Stuart
Robinson recognized this years ago: “You are now ready to ask—What then
is the nature and purpose of the Sinai revelations: and what place and
relation do they hold in the gospel system? The answer to this question is
not left to our conjecture or to mere ingenious inference. In much fuller
detail than in the case of any of the preceding revelations is the whole
matter expounded for us by the Scriptures themselves. This is a covenant
transaction, and this law, so called, constitutes simply the
stipulations of that covenant. So it is expressly declared of it, ‘The
Lord our God made a covenant with us at Horeb.’ It was ratified
formally, as a covenant, when first received, the people being called
upon solemnly to swear it, after it had been written down in a book” (Discourses
of Redemption [Richmond: Presbyterian Committee of Publication, 1866]
124, emphases mine). It should be noted, however, that Robinson was
completely unsympathetic with the thesis here proposed. Later Robinson said:
“It is no theory of mine, therefore, but the Holy Ghost’s, that this
Sinai law is our law. And just as truly was it with you and me, brethren,
‘who are alive this day,’ that he made that covenant” (p. 138;
emphasis mine).